Moral thinking: foundations, approaches and applications Henry Haslam www.moralmind.co.uk Introduction: free thinking
Good morning. It is a great privilege to be invited to speak here, in
the Conway Hall, home of the South Place Ethical Society, with its
fine tradition of promoting moral discourse and free thinking. To
me, as a Christian, the Christian faith makes an excellent starting
point for free thinking – for the scientific, philosophical and
intellectual exploration of the universe and, specifically, of the
human personality. The dictionaries tell me that that ‘free-thinker’
is commonly used to refer to those who reject religious teaching,
but I hope that for today you will permit me to liberate the term
from these atheistic moorings, cast out into the open water, and, as
a Christian, indulge in a bit of free thinking.
My subject today is moral thinking. Although for many people moral
thinking is associated with religious belief, the two are not identical
– indeed, they are sometimes in conflict. The moral mind is
something that believers and non-believers have in common, and
there are many opportunities for agreement – and for fruitful
Reason and rationality
It is sometimes said that one approach to morality and the general
question of how to live is based on reason or rationality, and I
would like first to look at what this might mean. Let us start by
Reason as a foundation for moral thinking 1. Reason v the authority of religion
A morality based on reason may be contrasted with one that is
based on religion and religious teaching. This is a useful distinction,
and can be compared with the old theological distinction between
natural and revealed theology: natural theology is what we can
learn about God from studying his creation and from human reason;
revealed theology is what we can learn from scripture and spiritual
experience. A great deal of modern Christian moral thinking is
either based on reason, in this sense, or at least is checked against
reason. The difference between believers and non-believers is not
primarily about ethics. We differ in our understanding of the world
and of our place in it, not about moral thinking. Religious believers
in parliament or on Radio 4’s ‘Thought for the Day’, for example,
tend to base their argument more on reason than on revelation,
using arguments that non-believers can engage with. It is true that
there are sometimes moral issues over which believers may differ
from non-believers on moral grounds: for example, many
philosophers from Aristotle to the present day would disagree with
Christian teaching that humility is a virtue. But there are many
controversial issues in which we can find believers and non-
Reason, then, means ‘not from divine revelation’ or not from the
authority of religion. That is rather negative. Does it mean anything
In practice, most of us base our moral thinking on our own
consciences – and this is true of Christians as well as humanists.
This leads to another way in which reason can be contrasted with
Reason as a foundation for moral thinking 1. Reason v the authority of religion 2. Reason v emotion, instinct or intuition
A morality based on reason can be contrasted with one based on
emotion, instinct or intuition. These are rather broad and ill-defined
terms, and I rather prefer the short and ill-defined word ‘gut’ for
these feelings, sentiments and convictions. Many of our moral
sentiments are gut feelings, or derived from gut feelings.
‘Morality is more properly felt than judg’d of.’ David Hume, 1740 ‘Reason is, and ought only to be the slave of the passions, and can never pretend to any other office than to serve and obey them.’ David Hume, 1740
These two famous quotations from the philosopher David Hume
The psychologist Jonathan Haidt says the same thing.
‘Morality is driven by emotions and intuitions, not reasoning.’ Jonathan Haidt, moral psychologist, 2010
Reason has a role in moral thinking, but it is the passions,
emotions, intuitions or gut feelings, that take the lead.
Modern psychology tells us that it is commonly the emotional part
of our nature that makes decisions; reasons follow later. I am one
of those people who like to make decisions – life’s little decisions as
well as the bigger ones – on a rational basis. As a consequence, I
am hopelessly indecisive. I can always see both sides. The people
who can make up their minds are the ones who just know what is
the right thing to do. They may wish to clothe their decisions with
reasons, but that comes afterwards. Benjamin Franklin understood
‘So convenient a thing it is to be a reasonable creature, since it enables one to find or make a reason for everything one has a mind to do.’ Benjamin Franklin, 1791
If reason is a tool for justifying whatever we have a mind to do, it
cannot be a secure foundation for moral thinking. It can, of course,
be a valuable tool for working out moral behaviour once we have
A third understanding of reason is through the term ‘reasonable’.
We know what we mean by a reasonable person – a sensible, level-
headed, right-thinking sort of person, someone whose moral
sentiments and thinking we can understand.
Reason as a foundation for moral thinking 1. Reason v the authority of religion 2. Reason v emotion, instinct or intuition 3. A reasonable person is someone who agrees with me
In other words, someone who agrees with me. Agreement about
moral issues is important. A community is held together by shared
moral values. It is generally right that we should fit in with the
moral conventions and values of the society in which we live. Laws
should command general consent, and it is generally right that we
should obey them. This agreement is important, but it is far from
being all there is to morality. There are three important riders. The
first is that morality should take account of minorities, who may
have different moral values. The second is that, in our globalised
world, we are more aware of societies with different moral
conventions, and we interact with these societies. Most of us know
people whose values differ from our own. We have to face up to the
fact that we do not all agree about moral issues.
The third rider is that if we all just followed convention, if we all just
kept agreeing with each other, we would still be owning slaves and
hanging people for stealing sheep, and we would be entertained by
watching bear-baiting, cock-fighting and public executions. Moral
thinking has an important role in challenging prevailing, accepted
values. The role of the reasonable person here is pithily expressed
‘The reasonable man adapts himself to the world; the unreasonable one persists in trying to adapt the world to himself. Therefore, all progress depends on the unreasonable man.’ George Bernard Shaw, Maxims for Revolutionists, 1903
So the idea of basing morality on reason or being reasonable
doesn’t seem to have much going for it, does it?
You can’t explain it
This brings us to perhaps the most frustrating, but also intriguing
and fascinating, thing about moral thinking. It is elusive. You can’t
pin it down. You can’t explain it in terms of anything else. Equally,
you can’t explain it away in terms of anything else. It’s not all a
matter of upbringing. It’s not all a matter of culture and convention.
It’s not all a matter of evolution. As we have seen, it is not just a
question of being reasonable or rational. All of these can help us to
understand particular aspects of our moral thinking, but none of
them explain why morality exists as one of the dimensions of reality
and none of them, on their own, offer a secure foundation to enable
Faced with this dilemma and with the inability to treat statements of
moral value in the same way as statements of scientific fact,
philosophers of the first half of the twentieth century reacted by
saying that such statements were meaningless, or that they were
so subjective as to be of little account. Led by thinkers like A J Ayer,
people came to fear that statements of moral value were not
intellectually defensible, that they were all relative, all just a matter
of personal opinion, and one person’s opinion is as good as anyone
It is certainly true that each of us has our own moral sentiments
and convictions, so morality is, to that extent, subjective… and yet…
and yet… there must be more to it than that. We cannot be
comfortable with a world view that has no place for the moral
dimension. There is a fundamental dilemma here, which was
‘I cannot see how to refute arguments for the subjectivity of moral values, but I find myself incapable of believing that all that is wrong with wanton cruelty is that I don’t like it.’ Bertrand Russell, 1960
He found that the evidence of his own inner convictions was at odds
with the theoretical ‘arguments’ that moral values are entirely
subjective. Russell, of course, was a philosopher: I am a scientist,
and when a scientist finds that evidence or observations conflict
with theory he is inclined to ditch the theory. Konrad Lorenz wrote,
‘It is a good morning exercise for a research scientist to discard a
pet hypothesis every day before breakfast.’
As a scientist, therefore, I would be inclined to set aside Russell’s
‘arguments for the subjectivity of moral values’ and take seriously
the inner conviction that not just Russell but nearly all of us have,
A scientific approach
How can a scientific approach help us to understand our moral
thinking? For many people, a scientist is someone who conducts
experiments in a laboratory, and it is an important part of the
scientific method that the experiments should be repeatable. Not all
science is like that, though. I used to be a geologist. My
experiments were too large to fit into a laboratory, and they took
millions of years to complete. For scientists like me, the scientific
method is not a matter of carrying out repeatable experiments; it
consists of making observations, trying to systematise them, and
What is our evidence? What evidence can we use for a scientific
study of moral thinking? Where is our starting point? The only
evidence available to us is the human experience. People do have
moral sentiments. We do hold moral opinions. We do make
statements about moral values. There is no other evidence. Leaving
aside the question of divine revelation, there is no evidence apart
from human experience. There is no observable external yardstick
against which we can check or measure our moral convictions. This
Moral conviction is no more subject to proof than the convictions of faith. Mary Warnock, Dishonest to God, 2010
As I said a few moments ago, any moral opinion that I hold is my
own, and in that sense, at least, it is subjective. But we do not think
that that is the end of the story. When we make a statement about
our moral convictions or values, we are reaching out, we are trying
to engage with something outside ourselves. Like Russell, we simply
cannot believe that the only thing that’s wrong with wanton cruelty
If we are to believe the evidence of the human experience (and why
shouldn’t we believe it?), the moral dimension is real, statements of
moral value are real statements about something that matters,
something that is more than a subjective personal opinion. Like all
our attempts to speak the truth, we may not be spot on every time,
but we feel that, somewhere out of reach, there is a truth that we
It becomes even more difficult when we look for the objective, or
rational, basis for any particular statement of moral value. In very
many cases it may seem quite easy. Generosity is universally
admired, for example, and stinginess disapproved of. Kindness and
courage are admired; cruelty and cowardice are not. But there are
also many issues on which we disagree. To take just one example,
if someone has done me harm, I may say that I should pay him
back, or that he should be punished; but you may tell me that I
should forgive him, or that I should give him another chance. These
are starkly different reactions to the initial act of wrongdoing, but
How far have we got, then, in our attempt to understand the
foundations for moral thinking? Not very far, really. There is little, if
anything, that can be proved, in a way that science would find
acceptable. All we have is the facts of different people’s moral
• The moral dimension is real
• Humans have the ability to engage with the moral dimension
To me, it seems reasonable to conclude from the evidence that the
moral dimension is real. We inhabit a moral universe, as Desmond
Tutu has put it. Secondly, humans, unlike other species, have the
mental capacity to recognise this moral dimension, to engage with
it, to make moral judgements, and to seek to understand what is
good behaviour and what is bad. This moral sense is part of the
One of the things about this moral dimension is that we think it is
important; we think it matters. There is an intensity in the voice
when we make moral assertions that we feel deeply about. We are
engaging with some of our deepest feelings. Our moral convictions
and values define the kind of people that we are.
Furthermore, these are the emotions that make us human. Charles
‘I fully subscribe to the judgement of those writers who maintain that of all the differences between man and the lower animals, the moral sense or conscience is by far the most important.’ Charles Darwin, The Descent of Man, 1874
One of the paradoxes of morality is that humans are the only
species to have a moral sense, but it doesn’t actually seem to do us
any good. We don’t behave any better than other animals. It is an
important part of our psychological make-up, but it is not a
particularly important driver of our behaviour. For my part, I agree
with Darwin, but there are many writers who don’t. There are books
written today about the human personality, and about what it is
that makes us human, in which the moral sense or conscience
If we stand back and compare human behaviour with the way other
animals behave, it doesn’t actually seem to make a lot of difference.
It is hard to maintain that humans as a whole live in a way that is
morally superior to the way other animals live.
• The moral dimension is real
• Humans have the ability to engage with the moral dimension
• It does not make us behave better than other animals
Bertrand Russell again. ‘Man is a rational animal [He says rational,
when he means moral – but we don’t need to go into that again].
Man is a rational animal’, he writes, ‘ – at least so I have been told.
Throughout a long life, I have looked diligently in favour of evidence
of this statement, but so far I have not had the good fortune to
come across it, though I have searched in many countries spread
over three continents. On the contrary, I have seen the world
plunging continually further into madness … I have seen cruelty,
persecution, and superstition increasing by leaps and bounds …’ and
I have tried to probe the foundations for our moral thinking, and I
have got as far as I can. From one perspective, that of the human
personality, it is supremely important; from another, an objective
assessment of the way humans live and behave, it seems to be
almost irrelevant. What is more, it continues to defy our attempts
to understand it and pin it down. Even what little I have been able
to put on this slide may be regarded as controversial.
The three approaches to moral decision-making
Let us move on, now, and look at the three main approaches to
The three approaches to moral decision-making 1. Moral principle 2. Consequentialist ethics 3. Virtue ethics
The first is moral principle. It is wrong to steal or murder, for
example. Kindness and generosity are good. The second is to judge
an action by its consequences. What are the benefits? What are the
The third approach is virtue ethics. Virtue ethics focuses on the
character of the person, rather than on the deed itself or its
consequences. It is a question of self-image, the kind of person I
want to be; it’s about my own integrity. The website of the South
Place Ethical Society carries the Shakespeare quotation ‘To thine
own self be true.’ This could be understood as a call to virtue ethics.
All three of these approaches can involve both gut and reasoning.
Gut starts us off, and reasoning can help us to apply our gut
For people who are unhappy about the subjectivity that is implicit in
moral principle and virtue ethics, it may seem attractive to put the
greatest emphasis on consequentialist ethics, believing that it is
more objective than the others. This attempt to be objective can be
partly, but not wholly, successful. Not entirely successful, because
consequentialist ethics has to rest on the premise that some
consequences are better than others – that pleasure is better than
hurt, for example. Consequentialist ethics, therefore, must be
founded on moral principle. It does not offer an escape from moral
principle. However, it does enable us to build a moral argument
based on simple moral principles about which we can all agree: that
pleasure is better than hurt, for example. We can then ignore other
moral sentiments that might be awkward or controversial. This can
lead to conclusions which conflict with those based on moral
principle. We shall see an example in a moment, when we come to
One of the things about virtue ethics is that it makes the point
particularly well that there is more to morality than altruism. There
is a school of thought that says that if you can explain altruism you
have explained morality. The argument runs that altruistic
behaviour can be explained by evolution by natural selection;
therefore morality can be explained by natural selection; therefore
there is no need of God. This argument is full of holes, but the only
point I want to make now is that there is more to moral thinking
Imagine you are a golfer in a tournament. Your ball falls in the
rough and you accidentally cause a slight movement of the ball
before taking your shot. Nobody else has seen. Do you acknowledge
this and accept the penalty, or do you keep quiet, and play on as if
nothing had happened? This is what happened once to the great
golfer Bobby Jones, when he was a young man. What did he do? He
reported what had happened, and a penalty was duly imposed.
When he was praised for his honesty, he replied, ‘You may as well
praise a man for not robbing a bank.’ The comparison with robbery
makes it clear that Jones regarded this as a moral issue – but it is
nothing to do with altruism, or compassion. It was to do with his
image of the kind of person he wanted to be. Morality is more than
Personal morality, social morality and the law
• Personal morality
• Social morality
• Political morality (the law)
We may distinguish three areas of life in which moral thinking may
be applied: first, our personal lives, with the decisions we make as
individuals about how we should live; secondly, the values that we
share with other members of our community, the kinds of behaviour
that we generally approve of or disapprove of; and, thirdly, the law.
Our personal morality is strongly controlled by our gut feelings, by
moral principle and virtue ethics. It may also be influenced by
religious belief. Consequentialist thinking then has an important
place in working out the applications. We develop our own personal
moral codes and values, accepting or rejecting other people’s values
as we see fit. Problems may arise when obedience to our own code
brings us into conflict with the code of our social group or with the
law, as when conscientious objectors come up against the law in
Social morality is more complex. Society contains a great diversity
of moral opinions and values. Sometimes, a sort of consensus can
be found on the sort of behaviour that we approve of or disapprove
of. On other issues, two or more different opinions may coexist
alongside each other. Because of this diversity, we have come to
attach greater importance to tolerance as a moral virtue. We then
have to decide how far we can extend our tolerance of other
people’s values. Most of us here today, I suspect, would not
condone execution as a punishment for people who have infringed
Next, the Law. Much legislation is based on moral values.
There is a sense in which morality is prior to, lies behind and is the foundation of the law. Mary Warnock, Dishonest to God, 2010
Baroness Warnock is a moral philosopher as well as being a
member of the legislature – a rare combination.
The moral values underlying some laws are obvious and non-
controversial: the laws against murder and theft, for example.
Other laws represent a choice between – or a compromise between
– opposing moral principles. I am thinking of abortion or assisted
Legislation on these issues is based on moral principle, and moral
principle may be one of the driving forces behind such legislation,
but consequentialist thinking is essential in drafting and debating
This is always how legislators have to make their moral decisions, in terms of the consequences that they foresee flowing from the Mary Warnock, Theos interview, 2010
An interesting political issue with strong moral overtones is that of
recreational drugs. There is general agreement that the misuse of
these drugs can have devastating effects for the individual and for
society. It is also well established that some illegal drugs cause less
harm than alcohol or tobacco, both of which are legal. These are the
Consequentialist arguments, based simply on benefit and harm,
lead us to two conclusions. The first is that some drugs, such as
cannabis and ecstacy are less harmful than their present
classification would suggest; they are wrongly classified. The second
is that the criminalisation of recreational drugs has not had the
desired effect. Decriminalising them would put the drug dealers and
drug pushers out of business. It would also vastly reduce the
incidence of theft, mugging and burglary, much of which is done to
feed a drug habit. And it would make it easier for addicts to make
contact with the people who could help them to overcome their
Against these consequentialist arguments are arguments from
moral principle, that the misuse of these drugs is wrong and to
reduce their classification or to decriminalise them altogether is to
send the wrong message. There is strong and widespread support
It is important to note, however, that the moral values held by
society are not necessarily enshrined in law. The law does not try to
cover everything that people disapprove of, and it cannot be a
substitute for personal responsibility. Too much regulation can
inhibit people from taking responsibility, and from making their own
professional and moral decisions. In the last few days we have
heard how social work is so beset by written instructions that the
real needs of the real child takes second place. Similar situations
arise in many other areas of work: healthcare, police, teaching –
Included with The Times recently was a supplement on business
‘Business ethics goes beyond compliance. Compliance can all too easily be about “ticking the boxes” so only the bare minimum is achieved, whereas business ethics is about striving to uphold the highest standards, above and beyond those that comply with the law, and doing the right thing even if no one is watching.’ Philippa Foster Back, director of the Institute of Business Ethics, 2010 ‘Where rules create loopholes and limits on behaviour, values do not. If those in leadership roles want to shape behaviour, they must pay more attention to instilling values.’ David Greenberg, executive vice president, LRN, 2010
These two quotations bring us back to virtue ethics: it is personal
values that count. You can’t legislate for virtue. The best hope is
that we should become a society that can see the value of values;
one where virtue is instilled, by example as well as by teaching, by
parents, by teachers, by leaders in every walk of life – and by the
The media
That leads us to the morality of the media. The media sit in
judgement on the nation’s morals. They take delight in exposing
any supposed wrongdoing, especially by people in the public eye.
And yet they themselves operate by moral standards that are quite
different from those that the rest of us would recognise.
The best journalists operate in accordance with high moral
standards, of course. A few years ago I came across the Code of
Conduct of the National Union of Journalists.
NUJ Code of Conduct 1. A journalist has a duty to maintain the highest professional and ethical standards. 2. A journalist shall at all times defend the principle of the freedom of the Press and other media in relation to the collection of information and the expression of comment and criticism. He/she shall strive to eliminate distortion, news suppression and censorship.
Look at that. First and foremost, before the principle of press
freedom, journalists have a duty to maintain the highest
professional and ethical standards. Or they did once. They now
NUJ Code of Conduct A journalist: 1. At all times upholds and defends the principle of media freedom, the right of freedom of expression and the right of the public to be informed.
The bit about ethical standards has disappeared, and the second
bit, somewhat altered, has taken its place. Now, a journalist ‘At all
times upholds and defends the principle of media freedom, the right
of freedom of expression and the right of the public to be informed.’
We have seen how consequentialist thinking has an important part
to play in moral thinking, particularly in public issues. If we apply
such thinking to the media, that would mean asking questions like
‘What benefit might come if this information is placed in the public
Most of us, if we are thinking ethically, would think it right to refrain
from giving lots of people information that was likely to cause hurt,
with no compensating benefit. Journalists are not like that. For
them, the right to freedom of speech is top of their code. If people
get hurt, or there is some damage to the public interest, that
doesn’t matter. What matters is their freedom of expression.
Consequently, we find that time and time again we see some story
in the public domain where the hurt or harm from putting it there
far exceeds the benefit. Time and again we see news items that just
should not be there. Often they concern people who are in no way
public figures. Often they concern people who are. A few examples.
During the course of a police investigation for murder, sometimes
suspicion temporarily falls on someone who happened to be near
the scene of the crime. Such people can be given the full media
treatment, even though the police later conclude that the person
Another example. Within the last year, it was the media who made
sure that the new government lost one its most promising
ministers, David Laws. It was the media who were clearly going to
make it impossible for David Miliband to remain a prominent figure
in the Labour party when his brother was party leader. It was the
media who, it was thought, would make it impossible for Lord
Young to continue as a government advisor. Three men who had
something to give to public life, removed by the whim of the media.
More recently, a national newspaper tricked a few government
ministers into being indiscreet. Great fun for the journalists, of
course, and their newspaper, but no benefit to the nation.
NUJ Code of Conduct A journalist: 5. Obtains material by honest, straightforward and open means, with the exception of investigations that are both overwhelmingly in the public interest and which involve evidence that cannot be obtained by straightforward means.
There’s another point here. For most of us, such deceit would be
contrary to moral principle, but, whatever their Code of Conduct
might say, the media don’t seem to live by the same standards as
Quite a different example, now. One of the threats that face us
today is the conflict between Muslims and the West, between the
values of Islam and those of Western societies.
The media delight in reporting inflammatory statements by Muslim
hotheads. They don’t report the moderate statements made week
after week by moderate, mainstream, peace-loving Muslims. On the
Christian side, when a small-town pastor in Florida, with no
previous reputation as a respected theologian or public servant,
announces his intention to burn the Qur’an, he gets worldwide
The media don’t report the excellent work done by interfaith groups
in our towns and cities, building up understanding and real
friendship between people of different faiths. They don’t remind us
of all the British Muslims who have a love for their country as well
as a love for their religion. They don’t remind us of all the Muslims
who share with most other people in this country a high regard for
our liberal, democratic traditions. They don’t remind us that where
many Muslims reject Western values – and I am thinking of our
self-indulgent, consumerist values – many other people in this
By choosing what to report, the media can promote understanding,
trust and friendship between Muslims and other sections of British
society, or they can promote distrust, fear and hostility, leading to
civil unrest, racial strife and sympathy for extremist, even terrorist,
views. The media have that choice, and it seems that they choose
The media don’t have to report everything they know. It is possible
to decide not to report. I seem to remember, years ago, the press
voluntarily keeping silence at the request of the police during
kidnap incidents. More recently, they kept quiet about Paul and
Rachel Chandler during their captivity, in obedience to repeated
court injunctions. I find it rather sad that they will only do the
decent thing if ordered to by the court.
Environmental ethics The three approaches to moral decision-making 1. Moral principle 2. Consequentialist ethics 3. Virtue ethics
I’d like to turn now to the question of environmental ethics: how we
treat the Earth, whether we care about the future. Can we apply
these three approaches to environmental ethics?
We are surrounded today, in our towns and cities, in our villages
and in the countryside, by reminders of the work and achievements
of past generations. Buildings of great beauty, both small and large
– the whole pattern of our townscapes and landscapes – for so
much of this we are indebted to our ancestors. We have so much to
We may then ask what contribution we, in our generation, are
making to the future. Not many buildings, or anything else, that will
delight the eye in a hundred years’ time. Worse than that, we are
using up the Earth’s supply of non-renewable resources, particularly
hydrocarbons, at an alarming rate, we are destroying peat lands in
this country, rainforests abroad and other natural habitats, and we
are polluting soil, groundwater, rivers, oceans and atmosphere with
In 2011 we have immense power over the future of this planet and
the human species. The planet we live on is life-giving and life-
Those are the facts. Some people think that this raises an important
Much of the argument is to do with consequences, but, as I said
earlier, consequentialist ethics rests on a foundation of moral
principle. We have to ask ourselves, is it a moral principle to care
about the future, to care about what happens after we are dead? Or
are we right to leave the future to look after itself?
Jane Goodall reminds us that our simpler ancestors were able to
plan with the future in mind: ‘It’s awfully sad’, she said, ‘that with
our clever brains … we seem to have lost wisdom; and that’s the
wisdom of the indigenous people who would make a major decision
based on how that decision would affect people seven generations
ahead. We’re making decisions based on the bottom line. How will
this affect me now? Me and my family, now? So although we think
we’re caring about our children and grandchildren, we’re actually
Then, let us look at buildings. All over the world, people have
constructed buildings to last well beyond their own lifetimes. In this
country, think of our great medieval cathedrals, some of them
taking many years to build. Long-term projects, with the future in
On an everyday level, when we make a will we are thinking of the
future, after we have died. This doesn’t represent a sacrifice on our
part, of course. For sacrifice, we can look at the armed forces,
people who risk their lives and often sacrifice them for the future of
their country and their families – for the sake of the future.
‘When you go home, tell them of us and say “For your tomorrows these gave their today.”’ J M Edmonds, 1918
What a contrast between the sacrifice evoked in this epitaph and
our me-first attitude when we insist on satisfying our wants today,
with little thought for all the tomorrows of future generations.
Putting all this together, I think there is enough evidence to show
that it is, or can be, part of the human personality to live our lives
in such a way that the future will benefit. I think we can call this a
Environmental ethics 1. Moral principle: to care for the Earth 2. Consequentialist ethics: identify the impact of our actions on the Earth, and reduce harmful actions 3. Virtue ethics: everyone has a contribution to make
Having established the principle, there is a lot of work for
consequentialist ethics, in working out the applications. If we look
at every aspect of our lifestyles, we can ask to what extent they
damage or enhance the environment. Green issues are much
discussed these days, and there are plenty of good ideas around.
Not infrequently, one moral principle comes into conflict with
another. Environmental ethics throws up many such conflicts.
Almost all powered transport is environmentally harmful, but
frequently we have sound moral reasons for travelling. We see
dedicated campaigning climatologists, for example, flying all over
the place to deliver lectures on climate change, telling us how
harmful flying is. It is up to each of us to find our own balance
Then, it is easy to point to the scale of the problem and say that my
own contribution is so tiny that there is no point in me doing
anything. I can’t make a difference. Even the contribution of the
United Kingdom is small, when we look at the global picture.
How can we answer this? Can we realistically expect people to do
their bit, when their bit is so insignificant? The first point to make is
that there are other situations where we act in the public interest,
even when we know that our personal contribution makes little
difference to the global picture and that it might be in our interests
to act differently. We have already noted the sacrifices made by the
armed forces. Another classic example is voting. One vote makes
no difference, and you’d rather be doing something else. But lots of
people still turn out to vote, and many regard the right to vote as
so important that they have campaigned to win that right. Another
example, highly relevant to the environment, is recycling. We see a
lot of people taking trouble with recycling their waste. They think it
is worth while, even when they know that there are other people
This is where virtue ethics comes in. Virtue ethics means that we
try to do the right thing even when other people do not, even when
the consequences seem insignificant in the grand scheme of things,
because that is the kind of person that we want to be. Virtue ethics
has a very important part to play in caring for the Earth.
There is an important role for governments. At home, they can
encourage environmentally friendly behaviour. On the world stage,
they can negotiate international agreements. Industry also has an
important role, in developing environmentally friendly technologies.
But even here, the role of individual people is decisive. Government
can only lead where the people are willing to follow; and there is no
point industry developing new technologies and new products if
people will not buy them. And, as I have said before, you can’t
Conclusions
That almost completes my free thinking for this morning. I hope
that one thing that has emerged is that on ethical matters there is a
huge amount of common ground between humanists and religious
believers. This applies particularly on social and political issues,
questions of public morality. Believers and non-believers can share
an understanding of moral principle, consequentialist ethics and
virtue ethics and can discuss ethical matters based on these
One important thing we share is the conviction that ethics matters.
Humanists and religious believers can join forces to remind people
that we are moral creatures, capable of change, and capable of
moral thinking and living. Humanists can tell the world boldly that
moral thinking is not just for religious people: it is for everyone.
There is another thing on which there is very wide agreement.
Moralists and reprobates alike all seem to think that a sinful life is
so much more fun, so much more satisfying, than a virtuous one.
Morality is irksome. Goodness is boring. Perhaps it is time that we
So, ladies and gentlemen, it is time to hand over to you, and I look
forward to hearing your comments, ideas and questions. Thank you.
Amaryllis House A review of the service model and the added value of the service for residents and their family/whanau Prepared by Alison Gray Amaryllis House Advisory Group January 2008 Acknowledgements This research could not have been done without the willing cooperation and generosity of many people. These include the residents of Amaryllis House and their family
The Arapahoe Sertoman Song: Rick Campbell Pledge: Dave Miley Prayer: Doug Harder Quote: “ Always do sober that which you said you’d do while you were drunk. That will teach you to keep your mouth shut”. Ernest Hemmingway Announcements Word is that Gus may be going home this weekend but don’t bother them yet until he says he is ready for visitors. Our new member, Jim